Well-Ordering Principle
Theorem
Every non-empty subset of $\N$ has a smallest (or first) element.
That is, the relational structure $\struct {\N, \le}$ on the set of natural numbers $\N$ under the usual ordering $\le$ forms a well-ordered set.
This is called the well-ordering principle.
Corollary
The well-ordering principle also holds for $\N_{\ne 0}$:
Let $\le_1$ denote the restriction of the usual ordering $\le$ to the set $\N_{\ne 0}$ of natural numbers without zero.
The relational structure $\struct {\N_{\ne 0}, \le_1}$ forms a well-ordered set.
Proof using Naturally Ordered Semigroup
Consider the natural numbers $\N$ defined as the naturally ordered semigroup $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$.
From its definition, $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ is well-ordered by $\preceq$.
The result follows.
As $\N_{\ne 0} = \N \setminus \set 0$, by Set Difference is Subset $\N_{\ne 0} \subseteq \N$.
As $\N$ is well-ordered, by definition, every subset of $\N$ has a smallest element.
$\blacksquare$
Proof using Von Neumann Construction
From Von Neumann Construction of Natural Numbers is Minimally Inductive, $\omega$ is a minimally inductive class under the successor mapping.
From Successor Mapping on Natural Numbers is Progressing, this successor mapping is a progressing mapping.
The result is a direct application of Minimally Inductive Class under Progressing Mapping is Well-Ordered under Subset Relation.
$\blacksquare$
Proof by Restriction of Real Numbers
Let $S$ be a non-empty subset of the set of natural numbers $\N$.
We take as axiomatic that $\N$ is itself a subset of the set of real numbers $\R$.
Thus $S \subseteq \R$.
By definition:
- $\forall n \in \N: n \ge 0$
and so:
- $\forall n \in S: n \ge 0$
Hence $0$ is a lower bound of $S$.
This establishes the fact that $S$ is bounded below.
By the Continuum Property, we have that $S$ admits an infimum.
Hence let $b = \inf S$.
Because $b$ is the infimum of $S$, it follows that $b + 1$ is not a lower bound of $S$.
So, for some $n \in S$:
- $n < b + 1$
Aiming for a contradiction, suppose $n$ is not the smallest element of $S$.
Then there exists $m \in S$ such that:
- $b \le m < n < b + 1$
from which it follows that:
- $0 < n - m < 1$
But there exist no natural numbers $k$ such that $0 < k < 1$.
Hence $n = b$ is the smallest element of $S$.
$\blacksquare$
Also known as
This is otherwise known as:
- the well-ordering property (of $\N$)
- the least-integer principle
- the principle of the least element.
Note that some authors cite this as the well-ordering theorem.
However, this allows it to be confused even more easily with Zermelo"s Well-Ordering Theorem, which states that any set can have an ordering under which that set is a well-ordered set.
Also see
Some authors extend the scope of this theorem to include:
- Set of Integers Bounded Below has Smallest Element
- Set of Integers Bounded Above has Greatest Element
Sources
- 1951: Nathan Jacobson: Lectures in Abstract Algebra: Volume $\text { I }$: Basic Concepts ... (previous) ... (next): Introduction $\S 4$: The natural numbers
- 1960: Paul R. Halmos: Naive Set Theory ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 13$: Arithmetic
- 1964: W.E. Deskins: Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.3$: Theorem $2.16$
- 1971: George E. Andrews: Number Theory ... (previous) ... (next): $\text {2-1}$ Euclid"s Division Lemma: Exercise $2$
- 1971: Allan Clark: Elements of Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Properties of the Natural Numbers: $\S 20$
- 1971: Robert H. Kasriel: Undergraduate Topology ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.17$: Finite Induction and Well-Ordering for Positive Integers: $17.2$
- 1972: A.G. Howson: A Handbook of Terms used in Algebra and Analysis ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 4$: Number systems $\text{I}$: Peano"s Axioms
- 1977: Gary Chartrand: Introductory Graph Theory ... (previous) ... (next): Appendix $\text{A}.6$: Mathematical Induction
- 1980: David M. Burton: Elementary Number Theory (revised ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Some Preliminary Considerations: $1.1$ Mathematical Induction
- 1982: P.M. Cohn: Algebra Volume 1 (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $2$: Integers and natural numbers: $\S 2.1$: The integers: $\mathbf{I}$
- 1994: H.E. Rose: A Course in Number Theory (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $1$ Divisibility: $1.1$ The Euclidean algorithm and unique factorization
- 1996: Winfried Just and Martin Weese: Discovering Modern Set Theory. I: The Basics ... (previous) ... (next): Part $1$: Not Entirely Naive Set Theory: Chapter $2$: Partial Order Relations
- 1997: Donald E. Knuth: The Art of Computer Programming: Volume 1: Fundamental Algorithms (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.2.1$: Mathematical Induction: Exercise $15$
- 2000: James R. Munkres: Topology (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $1$: Set Theory and Logic: $\S 4$: The Integers and the Real Numbers
- 2021: Richard Earl and James Nicholson: The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics (6th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): well ordered