Skip to content

jeltsch/modal-programming

Repository files navigation

Modal programming in Haskell

Haskell 2010 extended with higher-rank polymorphism is approximately System Fω and thus roughly corresponds to intuitionistic higher-order propositional logic via a Curry–Howard isomorphism. GHC’s static pointers extension, while having been conceived specifically for distributed programming, further extends Haskell such that it becomes a kind of generic modal programming language. This allows programmers to write libraries that turn Haskell into the Curry–Howard correspondents of various modal logics and to combine these libraries to arrive at programming languages that integrate multiple modal features. The modal-programming package provides support for writing such libraries.

Modal logics and modal programming languages

A propositional modal logic usually extends a non-modal propositional logic with the following components:

  • Modalities, which turn propositions into propositions

  • Axioms that involve these modalities

  • A rule, called N, which is of the form “if A is a theorem, then UA is a theorem”, where U is a dedicated modality

Therefore, we can build a modal programming language by adding the following constructs to a non-modal programming language:

  • Modalities, which turn types into types

  • Primitive values whose types involve these modalities

  • A new form of expression, absolutee, that has type Universalτ, provided that e is a closed expression of type τ, where Universal is a dedicated modality

The crucial points in the above lists are the last ones. Let us look at these in more detail.

In a modal logic, one assumes the existence of different worlds. Truth of a proposition depends on the choice of a world, and a theorem is a proposition that is true in every world. Analogously, in a modal programming language, the set of inhabitants of a type depends on the choice of a world, and there is a notion of absolute values: values that exist in every world.

A proposition A is a theorem exactly if it is true unconditionally, that is, if ⊢ A. Therefore, rule N can be formulated, “if ⊢ A, then ⊢ UA”. Analogously, a value is absolute exactly if it arises as the result of a closed expression, that is, an expression e for which ⊢ e : τ for some type τ. Therefore, the typing rule for absolute expressions can be formulated, “if ⊢ e : τ, then ⊢ absolutee : Universalτ”.

While a closed expression is an expression that does not contain any free variables, we can permit the expressions e in expressions absolutee to mention global variables, because we can always replace global variables by the right-hand sides of their definitions. Therefore, we ultimately define an absolute value as the result of an expression whose free variables are all global.

Encoding of modal logics and modal programming languages

The modalities of a modal logic can be encoded in higher-order propositional logic as predicates on propositions, and the axioms that involve these modalities can be rephrased using the encodings of these modalities. Analogously, the modalities of a modal programming language can be encoded in System Fω as types of kind ∗ → ∗ and thus in Haskell as types of kind Type -> Type, and the primitive values whose types involve these modalities can be encoded as primitive values whose types involve the encodings of these modalities instead.

Unfortunately, it is impossible to encode rule N in higher-order propositional logic, and analogously it is impossible to encode absolute expressions in System Fω. In Haskell, however, we can encode absolute using the static construct that comes with GHC’s static pointers extension.

The modal-programming package

The modal-programming package provides support for implementing Curry–Howard correspondents of various modal logics. It comprises a type class of universal modalities as well as various modal analogs of type classes that reflect constructs from category theory, like Functor and Monad.