Jump to content

Ordinal arithmetic

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Ordinal exponentiation)

In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an explicit well-ordered set that represents the result of the operation or by using transfinite recursion. Cantor normal form provides a standardized way of writing ordinals. In addition to these usual ordinal operations, there are also the "natural" arithmetic of ordinals and the nimber operations.

Addition

[edit]

The sum of two well-ordered sets S and T is the ordinal representing the variant of lexicographical order with least significant position first, on the union of the Cartesian products S × {0} and T × {1}. This way, every element of S is smaller than every element of T, comparisons within S keep the order they already have, and likewise for comparisons within T.

The definition of addition α β can also be given by transfinite recursion on β. When the right addend β = 0, ordinary addition gives α 0 = α for any α. For β > 0, the value of α β is the smallest ordinal strictly greater than the sum of α and δ for all δ < β. Writing the successor and limit ordinals cases separately:

  • α 0 = α
  • α S(β) = S(α β), where S denotes the successor function.
  • when β is a limit ordinal.

Ordinal addition on the natural numbers is the same as standard addition. The first transfinite ordinal is ω, the set of all natural numbers, followed by ω 1, ω 2, etc. The ordinal ω ω is obtained by two copies of the natural numbers ordered in the usual fashion and the second copy completely to the right of the first. Writing 0' < 1' < 2' < ... for the second copy, ω ω looks like

0 < 1 < 2 < 3 < ... < 0' < 1' < 2' < ...

This is different from ω because in ω only 0 does not have a direct predecessor while in ω ω the two elements 0 and 0' do not have direct predecessors.

Properties

[edit]

Ordinal addition is, in general, not commutative. For example, 3 ω = ω since the order relation for 3 ω is 0 < 1 < 2 < 0' < 1' < 2' < ..., which can be relabeled to ω. In contrast ω 3 is not equal to ω since the order relation 0 < 1 < 2 < ... < 0' < 1' < 2' has a largest element (namely, 2') and ω does not (ω and ω 3 are equipotent, but not order isomorphic).

Ordinal addition is still associative; one can see for example that (ω 4) ω = ω (4 ω) = ω ω.

Addition is strictly increasing and continuous in the right argument:

but the analogous relation does not hold for the left argument; instead we only have:

Ordinal addition is left-cancellative: if α β = α γ, then β = γ. Furthermore, one can define left subtraction for ordinals βα: there is a unique γ such that α = β γ. On the other hand, right cancellation does not work:

but

Nor does right subtraction, even when βα: for example, there does not exist any γ such that γ 42 = ω.

If the ordinals less than α are closed under addition and contain 0, then α is occasionally called a γ-number (see additively indecomposable ordinal). These are exactly the ordinals of the form ωβ.

Multiplication

[edit]
The disjoint union { (n,0) : nN } { (n,1) : nN } , using lexicographic order with least significant position first, has order type ω • 2. This is different from ω.
The set { (0,n), (1,n) : nN } , under lexicographic order with least significant position first, has order type 2 • ω, which is equal to ω.

The Cartesian product, S × T, of two well-ordered sets S and T can be well-ordered by a variant of lexicographical order that puts the least significant position first. Effectively, each element of T is replaced by a disjoint copy of S. The order-type of the Cartesian product is the ordinal that results from multiplying the order-types of S and T.

The definition of multiplication can also be given by transfinite recursion on β. When the right factor β = 0, ordinary multiplication gives α · 0 = 0 for any α. For β > 0, the value of α · β is the smallest ordinal greater than or equal to (α · δ) α for all δ < β. Writing the successor and limit ordinals cases separately:

  • α · 0 = 0.
  • α · S(β) = (α · β) α, for a successor ordinal S(β).
  • , when β is a limit ordinal.

As an example, here is the order relation for ω · 2:

00 < 10 < 20 < 30 < ... < 01 < 11 < 21 < 31 < ...,

which has the same order type as ω ω. In contrast, 2 · ω looks like this:

00 < 10 < 01 < 11 < 02 < 12 < 03 < 13 < ...

and after relabeling, this looks just like ω. Thus, ω · 2 = ω ωω = 2 · ω, showing that multiplication of ordinals is not in general commutative, c.f. pictures.

As is the case with addition, ordinal multiplication on the natural numbers is the same as standard multiplication.

Properties

[edit]

α · 0 = 0 · α = 0, and the zero-product property holds: α · β = 0 → α = 0 or β = 0. The ordinal 1 is a multiplicative identity, α · 1 = 1 · α = α. Multiplication is associative, (α · β) · γ = α · (β · γ). Multiplication is strictly increasing and continuous in the right argument: (α < β and γ > 0) → γ·α < γ·β. Multiplication is not strictly increasing in the left argument, for example, 1 < 2 but 1 · ω = 2 · ω = ω. However, it is (non-strictly) increasing, i.e. αβα·γβ·γ.

Multiplication of ordinals is not in general commutative. Specifically, a natural number greater than 1 never commutes with any infinite ordinal, and two infinite ordinals α and β commute if and only if αm = βn for some nonzero natural numbers m and n. The relation "α commutes with β" is an equivalence relation on the ordinals greater than 1, and all equivalence classes are countably infinite.

Distributivity holds, on the left: α(β γ) = αβ αγ. However, the distributive law on the right (β γ)α = βα γα is not generally true: (1 1) · ω = 2 · ω = ω while 1 · ω 1 · ω = ω ω, which is different. There is a left cancellation law: If α > 0 and α · β = α · γ, then β = γ. Right cancellation does not work, e.g. 1 · ω = 2 · ω = ω, but 1 and 2 are different. A left division with remainder property holds: for all α and β, if β > 0, then there are unique γ and δ such that α = β · γ δ and δ < β. Right division does not work: there is no α such that α · ωωω ≤ (α 1) · ω.

The ordinal numbers form a left near-semiring, but do not form a ring. Hence the ordinals are not a Euclidean domain, since they are not even a ring; furthermore the Euclidean "norm" would be ordinal-valued using the left division here.

A δ-number (see Multiplicatively indecomposable ordinal) is an ordinal β greater than 1 such that αβ = β whenever 0 < α < β. These consist of the ordinal 2 and the ordinals of the form β = ωωγ.

Exponentiation

[edit]

The definition of exponentiation via order types is most easily explained using Von Neumann's definition of an ordinal as the set of all smaller ordinals. Then, to construct a set of order type αβ consider the set of all functions f : βα such that f(x) = 0 for all but finitely many elements xβ (essentially, we consider the functions with finite support). This set is ordered lexicographically with the least significant position first: we write f < g if and only if there exists xβ with f(x) < g(x) and f(y) = g(y) for all yβ with x < y. This is a well-ordering and hence gives an ordinal number.

The definition of exponentiation can also be given by transfinite recursion on the exponent β. When the exponent β = 0, ordinary exponentiation gives α0 = 1 for any α. For β > 0, the value of αβ is the smallest ordinal greater than or equal to αδ · α for all δ < β. Writing the successor and limit ordinals cases separately:

  • α0 = 1.
  • αS(β) = (αβ) · α, for a successor ordinal S(β).
  • , when β is a limit ordinal.

Both definitions simplify considerably if the exponent β is a finite number: αβ is then just the product of β copies of α; e.g. ω3 = ω·ω·ω, and the elements of ω3 can be viewed as triples of natural numbers, ordered lexicographically with least significant position first. This agrees with the ordinary exponentiation of natural numbers.

But for infinite exponents, the definition may not be obvious. For example, αω can be identified with a set of finite sequences of elements of α, properly ordered. The equation 2ω = ω expresses the fact that finite sequences of zeros and ones can be identified with natural numbers, using the binary number system. The ordinal ωω can be viewed as the order type of finite sequences of natural numbers; every element of ωω (i.e. every ordinal smaller than ωω) can be uniquely written in the form where k, n1, ..., nk are natural numbers, c1, ..., ck are nonzero natural numbers, and n1 > ... > nk.

The same is true in general: every element of αβ (i.e. every ordinal smaller than αβ) can be uniquely written in the form where k is a natural number, b1, ..., bk are ordinals smaller than β with b1 > ... > bk, and a1, ..., ak are nonzero ordinals smaller than α. This expression corresponds to the function f : βα which sends bi to ai for i = 1, ..., k and sends all other elements of β to 0.

While the same exponent-notation is used for ordinal exponentiation and cardinal exponentiation, the two operations are quite different and should not be confused. The cardinal exponentiation AB is defined to be the cardinal number of the set of all functions BA, while the ordinal exponentiation αβ only contains the functions βα with finite support, typically a set of much smaller cardinality. To avoid confusing ordinal exponentiation with cardinal exponentiation, one can use symbols for ordinals (e.g. ω) in the former and symbols for cardinals (e.g. ) in the latter.

Properties

[edit]
  • α0 = 1.
  • If 0 < α, then 0α = 0.
  • 1α = 1.
  • α1 = α.
  • αβ·αγ = αβ γ.
  • (αβ)γ = αβ·γ.
  • There are α, β, and γ for which (α · β)γαγ · βγ. For instance, (ω · 2)2 = ω·2·ω·2 = ω2 · 2 ≠ ω2 · 4.
  • Ordinal exponentiation is strictly increasing and continuous in the right argument: If γ > 1 and α < β, then γα < γβ.
  • If α < β, then αγβγ. Note, for instance, that 2 < 3 and yet 2ω = 3ω = ω.
  • If α > 1 and αβ = αγ, then β = γ. If α = 1 or α = 0 this is not the case.
  • For all α and β, if β > 1 and α > 0 then there exist unique γ, δ, and ρ such that α = βγ · δ ρ such that 0 < δ < β and ρ < βγ.

Jacobsthal showed that the only solutions of αβ = βα with αβ are given by α = β, or α = 2 and β = 4, or α is any limit ordinal and β = εα where ε is an ε-number larger than α.[1]

Beyond exponentiation

[edit]

There are ordinal operations that continue the sequence begun by addition, multiplication, and exponentiation, including ordinal versions of tetration, pentation, and hexation. See also Veblen function.

Cantor normal form

[edit]

Every ordinal number α can be uniquely written as , where k is a natural number, are nonzero natural numbers, and are ordinal numbers. The degenerate case α = 0 occurs when k = 0 and there are no βs nor cs. This decomposition of α is called the Cantor normal form of α, and can be considered the base-ω positional numeral system. The highest exponent is called the degree of , and satisfies . The equality applies if and only if . In that case Cantor normal form does not express the ordinal in terms of smaller ones; this can happen as explained below.

A minor variation of Cantor normal form, which is usually slightly easier to work with, is to set all the numbers ci equal to 1 and allow the exponents to be equal. In other words, every ordinal number α can be uniquely written as , where k is a natural number, and are ordinal numbers.

Another variation of the Cantor normal form is the "base δ expansion", where ω is replaced by any ordinal δ > 1, and the numbers ci are nonzero ordinals less than δ.

The Cantor normal form allows us to uniquely express—and order—the ordinals α that are built from the natural numbers by a finite number of arithmetical operations of addition, multiplication and exponentiation base-: in other words, assuming in the Cantor normal form, we can also express the exponents in Cantor normal form, and making the same assumption for the as for α and so on recursively, we get a system of notation for these ordinals (for example,

denotes an ordinal).

The ordinal ε0 (epsilon nought) is the set of ordinal values α of the finite-length arithmetical expressions of Cantor normal form that are hereditarily non-trivial where non-trivial means β1<α when 0<α. It is the smallest ordinal that does not have a finite arithmetical expression in terms of ω, and the smallest ordinal such that , i.e. in Cantor normal form the exponent is not smaller than the ordinal itself. It is the limit of the sequence

The ordinal ε0 is important for various reasons in arithmetic (essentially because it measures the proof-theoretic strength of the first-order Peano arithmetic: that is, Peano's axioms can show transfinite induction up to any ordinal less than ε0 but not up to ε0 itself).

The Cantor normal form also allows us to compute sums and products of ordinals: to compute the sum, for example, one need merely know (see the properties listed in § Addition and § Multiplication) that

if (if one can apply the distributive law on the left and rewrite this as , and if the expression is already in Cantor normal form); and to compute products, the essential facts are that when is in Cantor normal form and , then

and

if n is a non-zero natural number.

To compare two ordinals written in Cantor normal form, first compare , then , then , then , and so on. At the first occurrence of inequality, the ordinal that has the larger component is the larger ordinal. If they are the same until one terminates before the other, then the one that terminates first is smaller.

Factorization into primes

[edit]

Ernst Jacobsthal showed that the ordinals satisfy a form of the unique factorization theorem: every nonzero ordinal can be written as a product of a finite number of prime ordinals. This factorization into prime ordinals is in general not unique, but there is a "minimal" factorization into primes that is unique up to changing the order of finite prime factors (Sierpiński 1958).

A prime ordinal is an ordinal greater than 1 that cannot be written as a product of two smaller ordinals. Some of the first primes are 2, 3, 5, ... , ω, ω 1, ω2 1, ω3 1, ..., ωω, ωω 1, ωω 1 1, ... There are three sorts of prime ordinals:

  • The finite primes 2, 3, 5, ...
  • The ordinals of the form ωωα for any ordinal α. These are the prime ordinals that are limits, and are the delta numbers, the transfinite ordinals that are closed under multiplication.
  • The ordinals of the form ωα 1 for any ordinal α > 0. These are the infinite successor primes, and are the successors of gamma numbers, the additively indecomposable ordinals.

Factorization into primes is not unique: for example, 2×3 = 3×2, ω = ω, (ω 1)×ω = ω×ω and ω×ωω = ωω. However, there is a unique factorization into primes satisfying the following additional conditions:

  • Every limit prime must occur before any successor prime
  • If two consecutive primes of the prime factorization are both limits or both finite, the second one must be less than or equal to the first one.

This prime factorization can easily be read off using the Cantor normal form as follows:

  • First write the ordinal as a product αβ where α is the smallest power of ω in the Cantor normal form and β is a successor.
  • If α = ωγ then writing γ in Cantor normal form gives an expansion of α as a product of limit primes.
  • Now look at the Cantor normal form of β. If β = ωλm ωμn smaller terms, then β = (ωμn smaller terms)(ωλμ 1)m is a product of a smaller ordinal and a prime and a natural number m. Repeating this and factorizing the natural numbers into primes gives the prime factorization of β.

So the factorization of the Cantor normal form ordinal

ωα1n1ωαknk (with α1 > ⋯ > αk)

into a minimal product of infinite primes and natural numbers is

(ωωβ1ωωβm)nk (ωαk−1−αk 1)nk−1 ⋯ (ωα1α2 1)n1

where each ni should be replaced by its factorization into a non-increasing sequence of finite primes and

αk = ωβ1ωβm with β1 ≥ ⋯ ≥ βm.

Large countable ordinals

[edit]

As discussed above, the Cantor normal form of ordinals below ε0 can be expressed in an alphabet containing only the function symbols for addition, multiplication and exponentiation, as well as constant symbols for each natural number and for ω. We can do away with the infinitely many numerals by using just the constant symbol 0 and the operation of successor, S (for example, the natural number 4 may be expressed as S(S(S(S(0))))). This describes an ordinal notation: a system for naming ordinals over a finite alphabet. This particular system of ordinal notation is called the collection of arithmetical ordinal expressions, and can express all ordinals below ε0, but cannot express ε0. There are other ordinal notations capable of capturing ordinals well past ε0, but because there are only countably many finite-length strings over any finite alphabet, for any given ordinal notation there will be ordinals below ω1 (the first uncountable ordinal) that are not expressible. Such ordinals are known as large countable ordinals.

The operations of addition, multiplication and exponentiation are all examples of primitive recursive ordinal functions, and more general primitive recursive ordinal functions can be used to describe larger ordinals.

Natural operations

[edit]

The natural sum and natural product operations on ordinals were defined in 1906 by Gerhard Hessenberg, and are sometimes called the Hessenberg sum (or product) (Sierpiński 1958). The natural sum of α and β is often denoted by αβ or α # β, and the natural product by αβ or αβ.

The natural sum and product are defined as follows. Let and be in Cantor normal form (i.e. and ). Let be the exponents sorted in nonincreasing order. Then is defined as The natural product of and is defined as For example, suppose and . Then , whereas . And , whereas .

The natural sum and product are commutative and associative, and natural product distributes over natural sum. The operations are also monotonic, in the sense that if then ; if then ; and if and then .

We have .

We always have and . If both and then . If both and then .

Natural sum and product are not continuous in the right argument, since, for example , and not ; and , and not .

The natural sum and product are the same as the addition and multiplication (restricted to ordinals) of John Conway's field of surreal numbers.

The natural operations come up in the theory of well partial orders; given two well partial orders and , of types (maximum linearizations) and , the type of the disjoint union is , while the type of the direct product is .[2] One may take this relation as a definition of the natural operations by choosing S and T to be ordinals α and β; so αβ is the maximum order type of a total order extending the disjoint union (as a partial order) of α and β; while αβ is the maximum order type of a total order extending the direct product (as a partial order) of α and β.[3] A useful application of this is when α and β are both subsets of some larger total order; then their union has order type at most αβ. If they are both subsets of some ordered abelian group, then their sum has order type at most αβ.

We can also define the natural sum αβ by simultaneous transfinite recursion on α and β, as the smallest ordinal strictly greater than the natural sum of α and γ for all γ < β and of γ and β for all γ < α.[4] Similarly, we can define the natural product αβ by simultaneous transfinite recursion on α and β, as the smallest ordinal γ such that (αδ) ⊕ (εβ) < γ ⊕ (εδ) for all ε < α and δ < β.[4] Also, see the article on surreal numbers for the definition of natural multiplication in that context; however, it uses surreal subtraction, which is not defined on ordinals.

The natural sum is associative and commutative. It is always greater or equal to the usual sum, but it may be strictly greater. For example, the natural sum of ω and 1 is ω 1 (the usual sum), but this is also the natural sum of 1 and ω. The natural product is associative and commutative and distributes over the natural sum. The natural product is always greater or equal to the usual product, but it may be strictly greater. For example, the natural product of ω and 2 is ω · 2 (the usual product), but this is also the natural product of 2 and ω.

Under natural addition, the ordinals can be identified with the elements of the free commutative monoid generated by the gamma numbers ωα. Under natural addition and multiplication, the ordinals can be identified with the elements of the free commutative semiring generated by the delta numbers ωωα. The ordinals do not have unique factorization into primes under the natural product. While the full polynomial ring does have unique factorization, the subset of polynomials with non-negative coefficients does not: for example, if x is any delta number, then

x5 x4 x3 x2 x 1 = (x 1) (x4 x2 1) = (x2 x 1) (x3 1)

has two incompatible expressions as a natural product of polynomials with non-negative coefficients that cannot be decomposed further.

Nimber arithmetic

[edit]

There are arithmetic operations on ordinals by virtue of the one-to-one correspondence between ordinals and nimbers. Three common operations on nimbers are nimber addition, nimber multiplication, and minimum excludance (mex). Nimber addition is a generalization of the bitwise exclusive or operation on natural numbers. The mex of a set of ordinals is the smallest ordinal not present in the set.

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Ernst Jacobsthal, Vertauschbarkeit transfiniter Ordnungszahlen, Mathematische Annalen, Bd 64 (1907), 475-488. Available here
  2. ^ D. H. J. De Jongh and R. Parikh, Well-partial orderings and hierarchies, Indag. Math. 39 (1977), 195–206. Available here
  3. ^ Philip W. Carruth, Arithmetic of ordinals with applications to the theory of ordered Abelian groups, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 48 (1942), 262–271. See Theorem 1. Available here
  4. ^ a b Altman, Harry (2017-11-01). "Intermediate arithmetic operations on ordinal numbers" (PDF). Mathematical Logic Quarterly. 63 (3–4): 228–42. arXiv:1501.05747. doi:10.1002/malq.201600006. Retrieved 2024-08-28.

References

[edit]
[edit]